Sorted by date | |||
page177from Building Ideas
The
real importance of this process is as part of the worker’s “self-creation”,
where the personality of the producer is invested in their product – this
existentialist idea also anticipates the work of William Morris, the pioneer
English socialist and leader of the Arts and Crafts movement. Instead, the
industrial product has become a mere anonymous commodity, prized for its “exchange-value”
rather than any “use-value” in itself, and the worker, at the same time,
becomes commodifed under this system, valued as a labour resource rather than a
unique human being.
Not
surprisingly, perhaps, Marx’s political views brought him into early conflict
with academia and even his work as a journalist was soon suppressed by the
Prussian state. In 1843 he moved to Paris in search of more progressive
surroundings, where he met a fellow German, Friedrich Engels, who became his
lifelong collaborator. Engels, who had been working hi his family’s textile
business in Manchester, gave Marx some first-hand experience of capitalism, as
well as much-needed financial support. In Paris his radical journalism met with
further opposition from the government and he was forced to move to Brussels
until the onset of the German revolution of 1848. By this time he had written
the famous Communist Manifesto for the Communist League he had helped establish
there. The revolution in Germany collapsed in 1849 and he then moved back from
Cologne to Paris before finally settling down to live in London. It was only
after his death in 1883 that his more famous philosophical writings began to
appear in print, with the exception of the first volume of his study of Capital
which he did see published in 1867.
Through
Marx accepted that capitalism had produced many benefits for society, such as
much greater prosperity through an increase in productivity, he saw no reason
for the unfair “relations of production”, where a minority seemed at liberty to
exploit the labour of the majority. As a final stage in the development of an “ideal”
society, one without class divisions or destructive “antagonisms”, he predicted
a social revolution that would resolve these contradictions and create a new
system of common ownership of the means of production:
|
|||
|
|||
|
|||
page176from Building Ideas
the possibilities for revolution based on
his analysis of historical progress. He saw that in the civilisations of the
past a particular society would tend to collapse when the “contradictions”
within the system had broken out onto the surface. As he wrote at the beginning
of his famous work, The Communist Manifesto:
The
history of all hitherto existing societies is the history of class struggles.
Freeman and slave, patrician and plebeian, lord and serf, guild-master and
journeyman, in a word, oppressor and oppressed, stood in constant opposition to
one another, carried on an uninterrupted, now hidden, now open fight, a fight
that each time ended, either in a revolutionary re-constitution of society at
large, or in the common ruin of the contending classes.6
Besides
the continuing exploitation of one class by another, in modern society a new
danger had arisen inside the system. As a consequence of the division of labour
within the capitalist mode of production, the new industrialised worker had now
become “alienated” from his work. By breaking up industrial process into a
series of specialized components, capitalism had robbed ordinary workers of any
meaningful connection with their work. As Marx somewhat lyrically described it,
referring to a previous system of production:
Supposing
that we had produced in a human manner; each of us would in his production have
doubly affirmed himself and his fellow men. I would have objectified in my
production my individuality and its peculiarity and thus both in my activity
enjoyed and individual expression of my life and also in looking at the object
have had the individual pleasure of realizing that my personality was
objective, visible to the sense and thus a power raised beyond all doubt.7
|
|||
|
|||
|
|||
page174from Building Ideasthe economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which rises a legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness.4
This is the now classic description of the “base
and superstructure” model, depicting the geological conception of history that
Claude Lévi-Strauss
was so enamoured with. The base consists of two components, firstly the “forces
of production”, being the raw materials, machinery and labour required for
producing industrial goods. The second part he called the “relations of
production”, referring to the ways in which the work is organized, such as in
the typical pyramidal structure of the capitalist corporate hierarchy.
The
superstructure which rises out of this base and which is, in Marx’s terms,
determined by it, consists of the social, political and legal institutions that
make up the society’s “consciousness”. Quite how deterministic Marx meant this
model to be is still the subject of much argument among scholars. Marx does,
however, suggest a direct link between the two components of the base, when he
says “the hand-mill will give you a society with the feudal lord, the
steam-engine a society with the industrial capitalist”.5 This presents a
slightly caricatured version of Marx’s thinking on the process of history
which, in the case of the base and superstructure relationship, was more
complex than first appears. In fact the reasoning behind Marx’s call for
philosophers to change the world lies with the problem caused by one section of
society being exploited by another. In Marx’s model the class that controls the
base thereby also controls the superstructure, and under capitalism this meant
the working classes being locked into their relations of production. With the
institutions of the superstructure being controlled by bourgeoisies, this meant
that the workers were prevented from gaining any understanding of their
exploitation. Various corollaries to this scenario soon followed in Marx’s
thinking, as he set out
|
|||
|
|||
|
|||
page174from Building Ideas
It
was consciousness that became the great pivot-point for Marx, about which he
tried to turn Hegel’s philosophy on its head, although more accurately he
described it as standing Hegel on his feet. He felt that the idealist approach
had tried to build a philosophy from ideas, while he was attempting to reverse
this and build an alternative from experience. Hegel had, according to Marx,
simply inverted the real course of history, so to correct this Marx constructed
a system more closely modeled on reality. He did borrow, however, Hegel’s
dialectical model, where progress is described as an interplay between consciousness
and reality. Where in Hegel this process leas to a refinement of concepts, with
Marx it transforms the material conditions of reality. In Marx’s terms this
amounted to a “dialectical materialism”, although he himself only ever referred
to it as the “materialist conception of history”. As he wrote in 1859, in one
of his few philosophical works to be published during his lifetime:
The
mode of production of material life conditions the social, political, and
intellectual life-process in general. It is not the consciousness of men that
determines their being, but, on the contrary, their social being that determines
their consciousness.3
Marx
seemed to suggest that as individuals we are restricted in our actions due to
the presence of an unseen structure that appears to limit the mind’s potential
for free thinking. In a model comparable to the structuralist conception of the
underlying systems of language, Marx set out the means by which this
deterministic process might take place:
In
the social production of their life men enter into definite relations that are
indispensable and independent of their will, relations of production which
correspond to a definite stage of development of their material productive
forces. The sum total of these relations of production constitutes
|
|||
|
|||
|
|||
page173from Building Ideas
change it.”1 To begin to understand the
work of Marx and the reason for his significant and lasting influence, it is
necessary to consider a few of his key concepts before discussing their broader
impact.
In
approaching Marx’s philosophy it is important to understand his situation in
history, as a student in Berlin in the aftermath of Hegel’s dominating
influence. Marx arrived in Berlin in 1836, just five years after the great
philosopher had died. Hegel had been teaching in Berlin as a professor of
philosophy since 1818 and had left a huge and lasting legacy which the next
generation now had to deal with. For Marx and a group of colleagues who called
themselves the Young Hegelians, the emphasis was on trying to locate the weak
points in the great edifice of Hegel’s system. We have seen in Chapter 1 how
Hegel had constructed a historical philosophy which presented the whole course
of history as the quest for absolute knowledge. Hegel had shown the force
behind this process to be emerging “world-spirit”, an “idea” attempting to
express itself in the physical forms of the visible world. The culmination of
Hegel’s history took place in the mind of the philosopher, being the ultimate
manifestation of “spirit” as it comes to its own self-understanding. This
idealism has gone down in history as one of Hegel’s grandest conceptions and it
is this great historical principle that soon attracted Marx’s attention.
Rather
than thinker with the minutiae in attempting to refine Hegel’s system, Marx set
out to attack its foundations by questioning its most basic assumptions. He
dismissed philosophical history as a dry academic abstraction, cut off from the
real history of everyday conditions and experience:
The
Hegelian philosophy of history is the last consequence, reduced to its ‘finest
expression’, of all this German historiography, for which it is not a question
of real, nor even of political, interests, but of pure thoughts, which
consequently must appear to Saint Bruno, as a series of ‘thoughts’ that devour
one another and are finally swallowed up in ‘self-consciousness’.2
|
|||
|
|||
|