Sorted by date | |||
page108from Building Ideas
This
quest for the heart of things has been phenomenology’s major objective, ever
since Husserl first set out his method of achieving a definition of “ideal”
essences. This highlights the persistent problem of conceiving the relationship
between the mind and the world, just as Kant had discovered in the eighteenth
century, in trying to resolve the argument between rationalism and empiricism.
As Kant concluded, our human faculties impose a set of limits on our potential
knowledge and in attempting to define these limits the search has since shifted
to the experience of the individual “embodied” subject. The problem for
phenomenology has been the extension of these individual insights, to apply to
other individual subjects as part of an “inter-subjective” realm. Like Kant’s
definition of beauty as something experienced subjectively, there is still a
huge leap of faith required to accept that judgements are agreed upon
universally. This rift between the individual and the diverse experience of the
larger society is a persistent problem in phenomenology which many critics have
been quick to point out.
In
architecture there lies the possibility that this problem might be alleviated
through the study of phenomenology’s insights as part of the wider cultural
world. This hope that phenomenology offers possibilities for resisting the
reductive ideology of modern science has been expressed by various writers as
part of a general disillusionment with the state of architecture in the
twentieth century. As the architectural historian Alberto Perez-Gomez pointed
out, in the introduction to his important work on the “crisis” in modern
architecture:
The
problem that determines most explicitly our crisis, therefore, is that the
conceptual framework of the sciences is not compatible with reality. The atomic
theory of the universe may be true but it hardly explained real issues of human
behavior. The fundamental axiom of the sciences since 1800 has been ‘invariance’,
which rejects, or at least is unable to cope with, the richness and ambiguity
of symbolic thought.15
|
|||
|
|||
|
|||
page107from Building Ideashand”, particularly the way the tool in use becomes “transparent” to the person using it. This idea of reaching out into the environment – in the sense of the tool as an extension of the body – becomes a major theme in Merleau-Ponty’s work, particularly in his unfinished writings published just after his death. Earlier, in his book The Phenomenology of Perception, he had described a common scenario, where a person driving a new car takes a period of time to become accustomed to its size. With experience the person can feel whether the car will fit through a particular opening, as the volume of the vehicle becomes gradually incorporated into the overall “body image”. Likewise in the case of a blind person who has to navigate with the aid of a stick, the tip becomes the point of sensitivity and a means of communication with the surrounding environment. The stick becomes a part of the body as the person eventually learns to feel things “through” it and, like Heidegger’s hammer, it “withdraws” from our perception as the world is experienced at the tip of the cane.13 In his essay “The Intertwining – the Chiasm” which appeared in 1964, he developed the concept of the “flesh of the world” as a means of further exploring this idea. The intertwining referred to in the title is again that of the individual with the outside world, which he saw as a kind of transitional zone where the flesh of the body interacts with the “flesh” of things. Instead of a barrier between the mind and the world, he saw the body as our means of contact – the only means we have available for the task of reaching out to understand the world: It is that the thickness of flesh between the seer and the thing is (as) constitutive for the thing of its visibility as (it is) for the seer of his corporeity; it is not an obstacle between them, it is their means of communication . … The thickness of the body, far from rivaling that of the world, is on the contrary the sole means I have to go unto the heart of the things, by making myself a world and by making them flesh.14
|
|||
|
|||
|
|||
page106from Building Ideas
surprisingly, away from the history of
philosophy as such, to consider instead the role that action plays in our
perception of the outside world. Although in this early work he had looked at
spoken language in terms of its origins in the “language” of gesture – to claim
that gesture was still an important factor in communication – he went on in his
later essays to look at other means of expression, such as how an artist might
use his body to communicate ideas in physical form. In the essay “Eye and Mind”,
published in 1961, Merleau-Ponty described the body as an interface between the
perceiving mind and the physical world. His interest in the work of art came
from its expression of this interaction, such as where the brush strokes in a
painting reveal the movements of the artist’s hand. This “encounter” between
the artist’s body and the natural resistance of the medium being used provides
a powerful image of the everyday process of interaction between the body and
the world. As another French philosopher, Henri Bergson, wrote in 1896: “The
objects which surround my body reflect its possible action upon them.”11
Merleau-Ponty say this reflection or revelation of the body’s actions in the
tectonic qualities of the work of art – this suggested the idea of continuity
between the body and the outside world.
The
American philosopher John Dewey, in the book Art as Experience, also used a
similar formulation to explain his understanding of the work of art:
The
epidermis is only in the most superficial way an indication of where an
organism ends and its environment begins. There are things inside the body that
are foreign to it, and there are things outside of if that belong to it … 12
He
suggested that as the biology of human life requires the taking in of air and
foodstuffs, then one could also interpret the use of tools as a kind of “incorporation”
of objects into the body. This discussion brings him close to the early
Heidegger, in his analysis of the “ready-to-
|
|||
|
|||
|
|||
page105from Building Ideas
escape what Michel Foucault would later
call the “prison-house of language” – and provide a clearer understanding of
the nature of “embodied” knowledge.
A Philosophy of the Body – From Bergson to Merleau-Ponty
Perhaps the most intriguing of those later
writers who took up this theme of embodiment is the French philosopher Maurice
Merleau-Ponty, who collaborated closely with Jean-Paul Sartre. The two men
founded the philosophical journal Les Temps Modernes in 1945 and continued to
work together on it until a disagreement forced them to part company. The same
year that the journal was founded saw the publication of Merleau-Ponty’s major
work, the results of his doctoral research entitled The Phenomenology of
Perception. In this work he first set out the effect that the body has on our
perception, through a series of detailed analyses based on case studies from
clinical research. By considering the way the senses work together in the
process of synaesthesia, and how perception provides the raw data that the mind
arranges into clear concepts, Merleau-Ponty hoped to show that language itself
is merely derived from our lived experience and thereby to reverse the priority
given to it in Heidegger’s earlier analysis. As he describes it in the preface
to his book:
To
return to the things themselves is to return to that world which precedes
knowledge, of which knowledge always speaks, and in relation to which every
scientific schematization is an abstract and derivative sign-language, as is
geography in relation to the countryside in which we have learnt beforehand
what a forest, a prairie or a river is.10
What
Merleau-Ponty is trying to describe is a kind of pre-linguistic understanding,
the notion that the world is already meaningful for us before it is “parceled
up” into language. His research led him, not
|
|||
|
|||
|
|||
page104from Building Ideas
While all four components are meant to be “presented”,
in the properly poetic activity of authentic dwelling, the discussion remains tantalizingly
vague about the practical application of these ideas in architecture. Where
Heidegger does become more specific is in his discussion of the definition of
place, which he sees as the initial task involved in the acts of building and
dwelling. On the other hand place is seen to be dependent on the articulation
of boundaries and edge-conditions-the boundary is not where something stops,
but where something actually “begins its presenting”8 – and at the same time,
places can be created through the intervention of a newly built object. He
illustrates this with the example of the bridge, which brings the river banks
into a new relationship, as it “causes” the banks to lie opposite to one
another and “gathers the earth as landscape around the stream”.9
These
ideas begin to suggest a role for architecture, in heightening our awareness of
the character of our surroundings, as did Heidegger’s earlier analyses in the
book Being and Time, where he considered the interpretation of items of
equipment. In the end, however, language retains its status as the privileged
medium or “house of being” and this view has caused much controversy ever since
Heidegger first presented the essay “Building, Dwelling, Thinking” as a
lecture. At the same conference, the Darmstadt Colloquium, which took place in
August 1951, Ortega y Gasset presented his paper (mentioned above) on pragmatic
fields. Their argument concerned the priority between action and contemplation,
or between existence and essence in the understanding of the nature of dwelling.
Ortega’s “project of life” had become a “project of though” in Heidegger’s
work, whereas the dialectical relationship between the two realms was still
undeveloped in either version. It was left to other philosophers to return to
this theme and to consider the specific role of bodily experience – to
|
|||
|
|||
|